The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) 📕
Those not self-conscious and self-willed are constantly acting from self-interested motives, but clothing these in various garbs. Watch those people closely in the light of Stirner's teaching, and they seem to be hypocrites, they have so many good moral and religious plans of which self-interest is at the end and bottom; but they, we may believe, do not know that this is more than a coincidence.
In Stirner we have the philosophical foundation for political liberty. His interest in the practical development of egoism to the dissolution of the State and the union of free men is clear and pronounced, and harmonizes perfectly with the economic philosophy of Josiah Warren. Allowing for difference of temperament and language, there is a substantial agreement between Stirner and Proudhon. Each would be free, and sees in every increase of the number of free people and their intelligence an a
Read free book «The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) 📕» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Max Stirner
- Performer: -
Read book online «The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) 📕». Author - Max Stirner
nativity. What a slave will do as soon as he has broken his fetters, one must
--await.
In Kaiser's pamphlet, worthless for lack of form as well as substance (*"Die
Persönlichkeit des Eigentümers in Bezug auf den Socialismus und Communismus*,"
etc.), he hopes from the State that it will bring about a leveling of
property. Always the State! Herr Papa! As the Church was proclaimed and looked
upon as the "mother" of believers, so the State has altogether the face of the
provident father.
Competition shows itself most strictly connected with the principle of
civism. Is it anything else than equality (égalité)? And is not equality a
product of that same Revolution which was brought on by the commonalty, the
middle classes? As no one is barred from competing with all in the State
(except the prince, because he represents the State itself) and working
himself up to their height, yes, overthrowing or exploiting them for his own
advantage, soaring above them and by stronger exertion depriving them of their
favorable circumstances -- this serves as a clear proof that before the
State's judgment-seat every one has only the value of a "simple individual"
and may not count on any favoritism. Outrun and outbid each other as much as
you like and can; that shall not trouble me, the State! Among yourselves you
are free in competing, you are competitors; that is your social position.
But before me, the State, you are nothing but "simple individuals"!(71)
What in the form of principle or theory was propounded as the equality of all
has found here in competition its realization and practical carrying out; for
égalité is -- free competition. All are, before the State --simple
individuals; in society, or in relation to each other -- competitors.
I need be nothing further than a simple individual to be able to compete with
all others aside from the prince and his family: a freedom which formerly was
made impossible by the fact that only by means of one's corporation, and
within it, did one enjoy any freedom of effort.
In the guild and feudality the State is in an intolerant and fastidious
attitude, granting privileges; in competition and liberalism it is in a
tolerant and indulgent attitude, granting only patents (letters assuring the
applicant that the business stands open (patent) to him) or "concessions."
Now, as the State has thus left everything to the applicants, it must come
in conflict with all, because each and all are entitled to make application.
It will be "stormed," and will go down in this storm.
Is "free competition" then really "free?" nay, is it really a "competition" --
to wit, one of persons -- as it gives itself out to be because on this title
it bases its right? It originated, you know, in persons becoming free of all
personal rule. Is a competition "free" which the State, this ruler in the
civic principle, hems in by a thousand barriers? There is a rich manufacturer
doing a brilliant business, and I should like to compete with him. "Go ahead,"
says the State, "I have no objection to make to your person as competitor."
Yes, I reply, but for that I need a space for buildings, I need money! "That's
bad; but, if you have no money, you cannot compete. You must not take anything
from anybody, for I protect property and grant it privileges." Free
competition is not "free," because I lack the THINGS for competition. Against
my person no objection can be made, but because I have not the things my
person too must step to the rear. And who has the necessary things? Perhaps
that manufacturer? Why, from him I could take them away! No, the State has
them as property, the manufacturer only as fief, as possession.
But, since it is no use trying it with the manufacturer, I will compete with
that professor of jurisprudence; the man is a booby, and I, who know a hundred
times more than he, shall make his class-room empty. "Have you studied and
graduated, friend?" No, but what of that? I understand abundantly what is
necessary for instruction in that department. "Sorry, but competition is not
'free' here. Against your person there is nothing to be said, but the thing,
the doctor's diploma, is lacking. And this diploma I, the State, demand. Ask
me for it respectfully first; then we will see what is to be done."
This, therefore, is the "freedom" of competition. The State, my lord, first
qualifies me to compete.
But do persons really compete? No, again things only! Moneys in the first
place, etc.
In the rivalry one will always be left behind another (e. g. a poetaster
behind a poet). But it makes a difference whether the means that the unlucky
competitor lacks are personal or material, and likewise whether the material
means can be won by personal energy or are to be obtained only by grace,
only as a present; as when e. g. the poorer man must leave, i. e. present,
to the rich man his riches. But, if I must all along wait for the State's
approval to obtain or to use (e. g. in the case of graduation) the means,
I have the means by the grace of the State.(72)
Free competition, therefore, has only the following meaning: To the State all
rank as its equal children, and every one can scud and run to earn the
State's goods and largesse. Therefore all do chase after havings, holdings,
possessions (be it of money or offices, titles of honor, etc.), after the
things.
In the mind of the commonalty every one is possessor or "owner." Now, whence
comes it that the most have in fact next to nothing? From this, that the most
are already joyful over being possessors at all, even though it be of some
rags, as children are joyful in their first trousers or even the first penny
that is presented to them. More precisely, however, the matter is to be taken
as follows. Liberalism came forward at once with the declaration that it
belonged to man's essence not to be property, but proprietor. As the
consideration here was about "man," not about the individual, the how-much
(which formed exactly the point of the individual's special interest) was left
to him. Hence the individual's egoism retained room for the freest play in
this how- much, and carried on an indefatigable competition.
However, the lucky egoism had to become a snag in the way of the less
fortunate, and the latter, still keeping its feet planted on the principle of
humanity, put forward the question as to how-much of possession, and answered
it to the effect that "man must have as much as he requires."
Will it be possible for my egoism to let itself be satisfied with that? What
"man" requires furnishes by no means a scale for measuring me and my needs;
for I may have use for less or more. I must rather have so much as I am
competent to appropriate.
Competition suffers from the unfavorable circumstance that the means for
competing are not at every one's command, because they are not taken from
personality, but from accident. Most are without means, and for this reason
without goods.
Hence the Socialists demand the means for all, and aim at a society that
shall offer means. Your money value, say they, we no longer recognize as your
"competence"; you must show another competence -- to wit, your *working
force*. In the possession of a property, or as "possessor," man does certainly
show himself as man; it was for this reason that we let the possessor, whom we
called "proprietor," keep his standing so long. Yet you possess the things
only so long as you are not "put out of this property."
The possessor is competent, but only so far as the others are incompetent.
Since your ware forms your competence only so long as you are competent to
defend it (i.e. as we are not competent to do anything with it), look
about you for another competence; for we now, by our might, surpass your
alleged competence.
It was an extraordinarily large gain made, when the point of being regarded as
possessors was put through. Therein bondservice was abolished, and every one
who till then had been bound to the lord's service, and more or less had been
his property, now became a "lord." But henceforth your having, and what you
have, are no longer adequate and no longer recognized; per contra, your
working and your work rise in value. We now respect your subduing things, as
we formerly did your possessing them. Your work is your competence! You are
lord or possessor only of what comes by work, not by inheritance. But as
at the time everything has come by inheritance, and every copper that you
possess bears not a labor-stamp but an inheritance-stamp, everything must be
melted over.
But is my work then really, as the Communists suppose, my sole competence? or
does not this consist rather in everything that I am competent for? And does
not the workers' society itself have to concede this, e. g., in supporting
also the sick, children, old men -- in short, those who are incapable of work?
These are still competent for a good deal, e. g. for instance, to preserve
their life instead of taking it. If they are competent to cause you to desire
their continued existence, they have a power over you. To him who exercised
utterly no power over you, you would vouchsafe nothing; he might perish.
Therefore, what you are competent for is your competence! If you are
competent to furnish pleasure to thousands, then thousands will pay you an
honorarium for it; for it would stand in your power to forbear doing it, hence
they must purchase your deed. If you are not competent to captivate any one,
you may simply starve.
Now am I, who am competent for much, perchance to have no advantage over the
less competent?
We are all in the midst of abundance; now shall I not help myself as well as I
can, but only wait and see how much is left me in an equal division?
Against competition there rises up the principle of ragamuffin society --
partition.
To be looked upon as a mere part, part of society, the individual cannot
bear -- because he is more; his uniqueness puts from it this limited
conception.
Hence he does not await his competence from the sharing of others, and even in
the workers' society there arises the misgiving that in an equal partition the
strong will be exploited by the weak; he awaits his competence rather from
himself, and says now, what I am competent to have, that is my competence.
What competence does not the child possess in its
Comments (0)