The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) π
Those not self-conscious and self-willed are constantly acting from self-interested motives, but clothing these in various garbs. Watch those people closely in the light of Stirner's teaching, and they seem to be hypocrites, they have so many good moral and religious plans of which self-interest is at the end and bottom; but they, we may believe, do not know that this is more than a coincidence.
In Stirner we have the philosophical foundation for political liberty. His interest in the practical development of egoism to the dissolution of the State and the union of free men is clear and pronounced, and harmonizes perfectly with the economic philosophy of Josiah Warren. Allowing for difference of temperament and language, there is a substantial agreement between Stirner and Proudhon. Each would be free, and sees in every increase of the number of free people and their intelligence an a
Read free book Β«The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) πΒ» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Max Stirner
- Performer: -
Read book online Β«The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) πΒ». Author - Max Stirner
English.]
(48) [It should be remembered that the words "establish" and "State" are both
derived from the root "stand."]
(49) [huldigen]
(50) [Huld]
(51) What was said in the concluding remarks after Humane Liberalism holds
good of the following -- to wit, that it was likewise written immediately
after the appearance of the book cited.
(52) [In the philosophical sense [a thinking and acting being] not in the
political sense.]
(53) [CrΓ©ation de l'Ordre," p.485.]
(54) ["KΓΆlner Dom," p. 4.]
(55) [einzig]
(56) [am Einzigen]
(57) [Einzigen]
(58) [heilig]
(59) [unheilig]
(60) [Heiliger]
(61) B. Bauer, "Lit. Ztg." 8,22.
(62) "E. u. Z. B.," p. 89ff.
(63) [Einzigkeit]
(64) [See note on p. 184.]
(65) [The words "cot" and "dung" are alike in German.]
(66) e. g., "Qu'est-ce que la PropriΓ©tΓ©?" p. 83
(67) [Einzige]
(68) [A German idiom for "take upon myself," "assume."]
(69) [Apparently some benevolent scheme of the day; compare note on p. 343.]
(70) In a registration bill for Ireland the government made the proposal to
let those be electors who pay Β£5 sterling of poor-rates. He who gives alms,
therefore, acquires political rights, or elsewhere becomes a swan-knight. [See
p. 342.]
(71) Minister Stein used this expression about Count von Reisach, when he
cold-bloodedly left the latter at the mercy of the Bavarian government because
to him, as he said, "a government like Bavaria must be worth more than a
simple individual." Reisach had written against Montgelas at Stein's bidding,
and Stein later agreed to the giving up of Reisach, which was demanded by
Montgelas on account of this very book. See Hinrichs, *"Politische
Vorlesungen*," I, 280.
(72) In colleges and universities poor men compete with rich. But they are
able to do in most eases only through scholarships, which -- a significant
point -- almost all come down to us from a time when free competition was
still far from being a controlling principle. The principle of competition
founds no scholarship, but says, Help yourself; provide yourself the means.
What the State gives for such purposes it pays out from interested motives, to
educate "servants" for itself.
(73) [preisgeben]
(74) [Preis]
(75) [Preis]
(76) [Geld]
(77) [gelten]
(78) [Equivalent in ordinary German use to our "possessed of a competence."]
(79) [Einzige]
(80) [Literally, "given."]
(81) [A German phrase for sharpers.]
(82) [Literally, "unhomely."]
(83) II, p. 91ff. (See my note above.)
(84) Athanasius.
(85) [Wesen]
(86) [Wesen]
(87) Feuerbach, "Essence of Chr.," 394.
(88) [gebrauche]
(89) [brauche]
(90) [Verein]
(91) [Vereinigung]
(92) [MuthlΓΆsigkeit]
(93) [Demuth]
(94) [Muth]
(95) [Literally, "love-services."]
(96) [Literally, "own-benefit."]
(97) [Literally, furnishes me with a right.]
(98) [EmpΓΆrung]
(99) [sich auf-oder empΓΆrzurichten]
(100) To secure myself against a criminal charge I superfluously make the
express remark that I choose the word "insurrection" on account of its
etymological sense, and therefore am not using it in the limited sense which
is disallowed by the penal code.
(101) 1 Cor. 15. 26.
(102) 2 Tim. 1. 10.
(103) [See the next to the last scene of the tragedy:
ODOARDO: Under the pretext of a judicial investigation he tears you out of our
arms and takes you to Grimaldi. ...
EMILIA: Give me that dagger, father, me! ...
ODOARDO: No, no! Reflect -- You too have only one life to lose.
EMILIA: And only one innocence!
ODOARDO: Which is above the reach of any violence. --
EMILIA: But not above the reach of any seduction. -- Violence! violence! Who
cannot defy violence? What is called violence is nothing; seduction is the
true violence. -- I have blood, father; blood as youthful and warm as
anybody's. My senses are senses. -- I can warrant nothing. I am sure of
nothing. I know Grimaldi's house. It is the house of pleasure. An hour there,
under my mother's eyes -- and there arose in my soul so much tumult as the
strictest exercises of religion could hardly quiet in weeks. -- Religion! And
what religion? -- To escape nothing worse, thousands sprang into the water and
are saints. -- Give me that dagger, father, give it to me. ...
EMILIA: Once indeed there was a father who. to save his daughter from shame,
drove into her heart whatever steel he could quickest find -- gave life to her
for the second time. But all such deeds are of the past! Of such fathers there
are no more.
ODOARDO: Yes, daughter, yes! (Stabs her.)]
(104) [Or, "regulate" (richten)]
(105) [richten]
(106) "Der Kommunismus in der Schweiz", p. 24.
(107) Ibid, p. 63
(108) [Cf. note p. 81]
(109) [Geistigkeit]
(110) [Geistlichkeit]
(111) Rom. 1. 25.
(112) [das Meinige]
(113) [die --"Meinung]
(114) P. 47ff.
(115) Chamber of peers, Apr. 25, 1844.
(116) "Anekdota," 1, 120.
(117) "Anekdota," 1, 127.
(118) [vernehmbar]
(119) [Vernunft]
(120) [Literally, "thought-rid."]
(121) [Sache]
(122) [Sache]
(123) 1 Thess. 5. 21.
(124) [Andacht, a compound form of the word "thought"."]
(125) [See note on p. 112.]
(126) [Einzige]
(127) [Eigen]
(128) [geeignet]
III.
THE UNIQUE ONE
Pre-Christian and Christian times pursue opposite goals; the former wants to
idealize the real, the latter to realize the ideal; the former seeks the "holy
spirit," the latter the "glorified body." Hence the former closes with
insensitivity to the real, with "contempt for the world"; the latter will end
with the casting off of the ideal, with "contempt for the spirit."
The opposition of the real and the ideal is an irreconcilable one, and the one
can never become the other: if the ideal became the real, it would no longer
be the ideal; and, if the real became the ideal, the ideal alone would be, but
not at all the real. The opposition of the two is not to be vanquished
otherwise than if some one annihilates both. Only in this "some one," the
third party, does the opposition find its end; otherwise idea and reality will
ever fail to coincide. The idea cannot be so realized as to remain idea, but
is realized only when it dies as idea; and it is the same with the real.
But now we have before us in the ancients adherents of the idea, in the
moderns adherents of reality. Neither can get clear of the opposition, and
both pine only, the one party for the spirit, and, when this craving of the
ancient world seemed to be satisfied and this spirit to have come, the others
immediately for the secularization of this spirit again, which must forever
remain a "pious wish."
The pious wish of the ancients was sanctity, the pious wish of the moderns
is corporeity. But, as antiquity had to go down if its longing was to be
satisfied (for it consisted only in the longing), so too corporeity can never
be attained within the ring of Christianness. As the trait of sanctification
or purification goes through the old world (the washings, etc.), so that of
incorporation goes through the Christian world: God plunges down into this
world, becomes flesh, and wants to redeem it, e. g., fill it with himself;
but, since he is "the idea" or "the spirit," people (e. g. Hegel) in the end
introduce the idea into everything, into the world, and prove "that the idea
is, that reason is, in everything." "Man" corresponds in the culture of today
to what the heathen Stoics set up as "the wise man"; the latter, like the
former, a -- fleshless being. The unreal "wise man," this bodiless "holy
one" of the Stoics, became a real person, a bodily "Holy One," in God *made
flesh; the unreal "man," the bodiless ego, will become real in the corporeal
ego, in me*.
There winds its way through Christianity the question about the "existence of
God," which, taken up ever and ever again, gives testimony that the craving
for existence, corporeity, personality, reality, was incessantly busying the
heart because it never found a satisfying solution. At last the question about
the existence of God fell, but only to rise up again in the proposition that
the "divine" had existence (Feuerbach). But this too has no existence, and
neither will the last refuge, that the "purely human" is realizable, afford
shelter much longer. No idea has existence, for none is capable of corporeity.
The scholastic contention of realism and nominalism has the same content; in
short, this spins itself out through all Christian history, and cannot end
in it.
The world of Christians is working at realizing ideas in the individual
relations of life, the institutions and laws of the Church and the State; but
they make resistance, and always keep back something unembodied
(unrealizable). Nevertheless this embodiment is restlessly rushed after, no
matter in what degree corporeity constantly fails to result.
For realities matter little to the realizer, but it matters everything that
they be realizations of the idea. Hence he is ever examining anew whether the
realized does in truth have the idea, its kernel, dwelling in it; and in
testing the real he at the same time tests the idea, whether it is realizable
as he thinks it, or is only thought by him incorrectly, and for that reason
unfeasibly.
The Christian is no longer to care for family, State, etc., as existences;
Christians are not to sacrifice themselves for these "divine things" like the
ancients, but these are only to be utilized to make the spirit alive in
them. The real family has become indifferent, and there is to arise out of
it an ideal one which would then be the "truly real," a sacred family,
blessed by God, or, according to the liberal way of thinking, a "rational"
family. With the ancients, family, State, fatherland, is divine as a thing
extant; with the moderns it is still awaiting divinity, as extant it is only
sinful, earthly, and has still to be "redeemed," i. e., to become truly
real. This has the following meaning: The family, etc., is not the extant and
real, but the divine, the idea, is extant and real; whether this family will
make itself real by taking up the truly real, the idea, is still unsettled. It
is not the individual's task to serve the family as the divine, but,
reversely, to serve the divine and to bring to it the still undivine family,
to subject everything in the idea's name, to set up the idea's banner
everywhere, to bring the idea to real efficacy.
But, since the concern of Christianity, as of antiquity, is for the divine,
they always come out at this again on their opposite ways. At the end of
heathenism the divine becomes the extramundane, at the end of Christianity
the intramundane. Antiquity does not succeed in putting it entirely outside
the world, and, when Christianity accomplishes this task, the divine instantly
longs to get back into the world and wants to "redeem" the world. But within
Comments (0)