The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers by Diogenes LaĆ«rtius (best free ebook reader txt) š
Description
These brief biographies of more than eighty philosophers of ancient Greece were assembled by Diogenes LaĆ«rtius in the early third century. He based these on a variety of sources that have since been lost. Because of this, his biographies have become an invaluable source of information on the development of ancient Greek philosophy, and on ancient Greek culture in general. Most of what we know about the lives and otherwise lost doctrines of Zeno the Stoic and Diogenes the Cynic, for example, come from what Diogenes LaĆ«rtius preserved in this book. Mourning what else we have lost, Montaigne wrote: āI am very sorry we have not a dozen LaĆ«rtii.ā
Steamy romance, barbed humor, wicked cattiness, tender acts of humanity, jealous feuds, terrible puns, sophistical paradoxes, deathbed deceptions, forgery, and political intrigueāā¦ while the philosophers of ancient Greece were developing their remarkable and penetrating philosophies, they were also leading strange and varied livesāat times living out their principles in practice, at other times seeming to defy all principle.
Diogenes Laƫrtius collected as much biographical information as he could find about these ancient sages, and tried to sift through the sometimes contradictory accounts to find the true story. He shares with us anecdotes and witty remarks and biographical details that reveal the people behind the philosophies, and frequently adds a brief poem of his own construction that comments sardonically on how each philosopher died.
Read free book Ā«The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers by Diogenes LaĆ«rtius (best free ebook reader txt) šĀ» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Diogenes Laƫrtius
Read book online Ā«The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers by Diogenes LaĆ«rtius (best free ebook reader txt) šĀ». Author - Diogenes LaĆ«rtius
The oblique cases are the genitive, the dative, and the accusative.
An axiom is that thing which is true, or false, or perfect in itself, being asserted or denied positively, as far as depends upon itself; as Chrysippus explains it in his Dialectic Definitions; as for instance, āIt is day,ā āDion is walking.ā And it has received the name of axiom, į¼Ī¾ĪÆĻĪ¼Ī±, because it is either maintained, į¼Ī¾Ī¹Īæįæ¦ĻĪ±Ī¹, or repudiated. For the man who says, āIt is day,ā appears to maintain the fact of its being day. If then it is day, the axiom put before one is true; but if it is not day, the axiom is false. And an axiom, a question, and an interrogation, differ from one another, and so does an imperative proposition from one which is adjurative, or imprecatory, or hypothetical, or appellative, or false. For that is an axiom which we utter, when we affirm anything positively, which is either true or false. And a question is a thing complete in itself, as also is an axiom, but which requires an answer, as for instance āIs it day?ā Now this is neither true nor false; but, as āIt is dayā is an axiom; so is āIs it day?ā a question. But an interrogation, ĻĻĻĪ¼Ī±, is a thing to which it is not possible to make an answer symbolically, as in the case of a question, į¼ĻĻĻĪ·Ī¼Ī±, saying merely āYes,ā but we must reply, āHe does live in this place.ā
The imperative proposition is a thing which we utter when we give an order, as for instance this:
Do you now go to the sweet stream of Inachus.85
ā®
The appellative proposition is one which is used in the case in which when a man says anything, he must address somebody, as for instance:
Atrides, glorious king of men,
Most mighty Agamemnon.86
A false judgment is a proposition, which, while it has at the same time the appearance of a real judgment, loses this character by the addition, and under the influence of, some particle, as for instance:
The Parthenon at least is beautiful.
How like the herdsman is to Priamās sons.
There is also the dubitative proposition, which differs from the judgment, inasmuch as it is always uttered in the form of a doubt; as for instance:
Are not, then, grief and life two kindred states?87
But questions and interrogations, and things like these, are neither true nor false, while judgments and propositions are necessarily one or the other.
Now of axioms, some are simple and others are not simple; as Chrysippus, and Archedemus, and Athenodorus, and Antipater, and Crinis, agree in dividing them. Those are simple which consist of an axiom or proposition which is not ambiguous (or of several axioms, or propositions of the same character), as for instance the sentence āIt is day.ā And those are not simple, which consist of an axiom or proposition which is ambiguous, or of several axioms or propositions of that character. Of an axiom or proposition which is ambiguous, as āIf it is day;ā of several axioms or propositions of that character, as āIf it is day, it is light.ā
And simple propositions are divided into the affirmative, the negative, the privative, the categorical, the definite, and the indefinite; those which are not simple, are divided into the combined, and the adjunctive, the connected and the disjunctive, and the causal and the augmentative, and the diminutive. That is an affirmative proposition: āIt is not day.ā And the species of this is doubly affirmative. That again is doubly affirmative, which is affirmative of an affirmative, as for instance: āIt is not not day;ā for this amounts to āIt is day.ā That is a negative proposition, which consists of a negative particle and a categorem, as for instance āNo one is walking.ā That is a privative proposition which consists of a privative particle and an axiom according to power, as āThis man is inhuman.ā That is a categorical proposition, which consists of a nominative case and a categorem, as for instance āDion is walking.ā That is a definite proposition, which consists of a demonstrative nominative case and a categorem, as for instance āThis man is walking.ā That is an indefinite one which consists of an indefinite particle or of indefinite particles, as for instance āSomebody is walking,ā āHe is moving.ā
Of propositions which are not simple, the combined proposition is, as Chrysippus states, in his Dialectics, and Diogenes, too, in his Dialectic Art, that which is held together by the copulative conjunction āif.ā And this conjunction professes that the second member of the sentence follows the first, as for instance āIf it is day, it is light.ā That which is adjunctive is, as Crinis states in his Dialectic Art, an axiom which is made to depend on the conjunction āsinceā (į¼ĻĪµį½¶), beginning with an axiom and ending in an axiom, as for instance āSince it is day, it is light.ā And this conjunction professes both that the second portion of the proposition follows the first, and the first is true. That is a connected proposition which is connected by some copulative conjunctions, as
Comments (0)