An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith (ebook reader macos .TXT) π
The causes of this improvement in the productive powers of labour, and the order according to which its produce is naturally distributed among the different ranks and conditions of men in the society, make the subject of the first book of this Inquiry.
Whatever be the actual state of the skill, dexterity, and judgment, with which labour is applied in any nation, the abundance or scantiness of its annual supply must depend, during the continuance of that state, upon the proportion between the number of those who are annually employed in useful labour, and that of those who are not so employed. The number of us
Read free book Β«An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith (ebook reader macos .TXT) πΒ» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Adam Smith
- Performer: 0226763749
Read book online Β«An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith (ebook reader macos .TXT) πΒ». Author - Adam Smith
science which pretends to explain them must naturally have been
the first branch of philosophy that was cuitivated. The first
philosophers, accordingly, of whom history has preserved any
account, appear to have been natural philosophers.
In every age and country of the world, men must have attended to
the characters, designs, and actions of one another; and many
reputable rules and maxims for the conduct of human life must
have been laid down and approved of by common consent. As soon as
writing came into fashion, wise men, or those who fancied
themselves such, would naturally endeavour to increase the number
of those established and respected maxims, and to express their
own sense of what was either proper or improper conduct,
sometimes in the more artificial form of apologues, like what are
called the fables of Aesop; and sometimes in the more simple one
of apophthegms or wise sayings, like the proverbs of Solmnon, the
verses of Theognis and Phocyllides, and some part of the works of
Hesiod. They might continue in this manner, for a long time,
merely to multiply the number of those maxims of prudence and
morality, without even attempting to arrange them in any very
distinct or methodical order, much less to connect them together
by one or more general principles, from which they were all
deducible, like effects from their natural causes. The beauty of
a systematical arrangement of different observations, connected
by a few common principles, was first seen in the rude essays of
those ancient times towards a system of natural philosophy.
Something of the same kind was afterwards attempted in morals.
The maxims of common life were arranged in some methodical order,
and connected together by a few common principles, in the same
manner as they had attempted to arrange and connect the phenomena
of nature. The science which pretends to investigate and
explain those connecting principles, is what is properly called
Moral Philosophy.
Different authors gave different systems, both of natural and
moral philosophy. But the arguments by which they supported those
different systems, far from being always demonstrations, were
frequently at best but very slender probabilities, and sometimes
mere sophisms, which had no other foundation but the inaccuracy
and ambiguity of common language. Speculative systems, have,
in all ages of the world, been adopted for reasons too frivolous
to have determined the judgment of any man of common sense, in a
matter of the smallest pecuniary interest. Gross sophistry has
scarce ever had any influence upon the opinions of mankind,
except in matters of philosophy and speculation ; and in these it
has frequently had the greatest. The patrons of each system of
natural and moral philosophy, naturally endeavoured to expose the
weakness of the arguments adduced to support the systems which
were opposite to their own. In examining those arguments, they
were necessarily led to consider the difference between a
probable and a demonstrative argument, between a fallacious and a
conclusive one; and logic, or the science of the general
principles of good and bad reasoning, necessarily arose out of
the observations which a scrutiny of this kind gave occasion to ;
though, in its origin, posterior both to physics and to ethics,
it was commonly taught, not indeed in all, but in the greater
part of the ancient schools of philosophy, previously to either
of those sciences. The student, it seems to have been thought,
ought to understand well the difference between good and bad
reasoning, before he was led to reason upon subjects of so great
importance.
This ancient division of philosophy into three parts was, in the
greater part of the universities of Europe, changed for another
into five.
In the ancient philosophy, whatever was taught concerning the
nature either of the human mind or of the Deity, made a part of
the system of physics. Those beings, in whatever their
essence might be supposed to consist, were parts of the great
system of the universe, and parts, too, productive of the most
important effects. Whatever human reason could either
conclude or conjecture concerning them, made, as it were, two
chapters, though no doubt two very important ones, of the science
which pretended to give an account of the origin and revolutions
of the great system of the universe. But in the universities of
Europe, where philosophy was taught only as subservient to
theology, it was natural to dwell longer upon these two chapters
than upon any other of the science. They were gradually more and
more extended, and were divided into many inferior chapters; till
at last the doctrine of spirits, of which so little can be known,
came to take up as much room in the system of philosophy as the
doctrine of bodies, of which so much can be known. The doctrines
concerning those two subjects were considered as making two
distinct sciences. What are called metaphysics, or
pnemnatics, were set in opposition to physics, and were
cultivated not only as the more sublime, but, for the purposes of
a particular profession, as the more useful science of the two.
The proper subject of experiment and observation, a subject in
which a careful attention is capable of making so many useful
discoveries, was almost entirely neglected. The subject in
which, after a very few simple and almost obvious truths, the
most careful attention can discover nothing but obscurity and
uncertainty, and can consequently produce nothing but subtlelies
and sophisms, was greatly cultivated.
When those two sciences had thus been set in opposition to one
another, the comparison between them naturally gave birth to a
third, to what was called ontology, or the science which treated
of the qualities and attributes which were common to both the
subjects of the other two sciences. But if subtleties and
sophisms composed the greater part of the metaphysics or
pneumatics of the schools, they composed the whole of this cobweb
science of ontology, which was likewise sometimes called
metaphysics.
Wherein consisted the happiness and perfection of a man,
considered not only as an individual, but as the member of a
family, of a state, and of the great society of mankind, was the
object which the ancient moral philosophy proposed to
investigate. In that philosophy, the duties of human life were
treated of as subservient to the happiness and perfection of
human life, But when moral, as well as natural philosophy, came
to be taught only as subservient to theology, the duties of human
life were treated of as chiefly subservient to the happiness of a
life to come. In the ancient philosophy, the perfection of virtue
was represented as necessarily productive, to the person who
possessed it, of the most perfect happiness in this life. In the
modern philosophy, it was frequently represented as generally, or
rather as almost always, inconsistent with any degree of
happiness in this life; and heaven was to be earned only by
penance and mortification, by the austerities and abasement of a
monk, not by the liberal, generous, and spirited conduct of a
man. Casuistry, and an ascetic morality, made up, in most cases,
the greater part of the moral philosophy of the schools. By far
the most important of all the different branches of philosophy
became in this manner by far the most corrupted.
Such, therefore, was the common course of philosophical education
in the greater part of the universities in Europe. Logic was
taught first; ontology came in the second place; pneumatology,
comprehending the doctrine concerning the nature of the human
soul and of the Deity, in the third; in the fourth followed a
debased system of moral philosophy, which was considered as
immediately connected with the doctrines of pneumatology, with
the immortality of the human soul, and with the rewards and
punishments which, from the justice of the Deity, were to be
expected in a life to come: a short and superficial system of
physics usually concluded the course.
The alterations which the universities of Europe thus introduced
into the ancient course of philosophy were all meant for the
education of ecclesiastics, and to render it a more proper
introduction to the study of theology But the additional quantity
of subtlety and sophistry, the casuistry and ascetic morality
which those alterations introduced into it, certainly did not
render it more for the education of gentlemen or men of the
world, or more likely either to improve the understanding or to
mend the heart.
This course of philosophy is what still continues to be taught in
the greater part of the universities of Europe, with more or less
diligence, according as the constitution of each particular
university happens to render diligence more or less necessary to
the teachers. In some of the richest and best endowed
universities, the tutors content themselves with teaching a few
unconnected shreds and parcels of this corrupted course ; and
even these they commonly teach very negligently and
superficially.
The improvements which, in modern times have been made in several
different branches of philosophy, have not, the greater part of
them, been made in universities, though some, no doubt, have. The
greater part of universities have not even been very forward to
adopt those improvements after they were made; and several of
those learned societies have chosen to remain, for a long time,
the sanctuaries in which exploded systems and obsolete prejudices
found shelter and protection, after they had been hunted out of
every other corner of the world. In general, the richest and best
endowed universities have been slowest in adopting those
improvements, and the most averse to permit any considerable
change in the established plan of education. Those improvements
were more easily introduced into some of the poorer universities,
in which the teachers, depending upon their reputation for the
greater part of their subsistence, were obliged to pay more
attention to the current opinions of the world.
But though the public schools and universities of Europe were
originally intended only for the education of a particular
profession, that of churchmen ; and though they were not always
very diligent in instructing their pupils, even in the sciences
which were supposed neccessary for that profession; yet they
gradually drew to themselves the education of almost all other
people, particularly of almost all gentlemen and men of fortune.
No better method, it seems, could be fallen upon, of spending,
with any advantage, the long interval between infancy and that
period of life at which men begin to apply in good earnest to the
real business of the world, the business which is to employ them
during the remainder of their days. The greater part of what is
taught in schools and universities, however, does not seem to be
the most proper preparation for that business.
In England, it becomes every day more and more the custom to send
young people to travel in foreign countries immediately upon
their leaving school, and without sending them to any university.
Our young people, it is said, generally return home much improved
by their travels. A young man, who goes abroad at seventeen or
eighteen, and returns home at one-and-twenty, returns three or
four years older than he was when he went abroad ; and at that
age it is very difficult not to improve a good deal in three or
four years. In the course of his travels, he generally acquires
some knowledge of one or two foreign languages; a knowledge,
however, which is seldom sufficient to enable him either to speak
or write them with propriety. In other respects, he commonly
returns home more conceited, more unprincipled, more dissipated,
and more incapable of my serious application, either to study or
to business, than he could well have become in so short a time
had he lived at home. By travelling so very young, by spending in
the most frivolous dissipation the most previous years of
Comments (0)