Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein (i want to read a book .txt) π
Description
Ludwig Wittgenstein is considered by many to be one of the most important philosophers of the 20th century. He was born in Vienna to an incredibly rich family, but he gave away his inheritance and spent his life alternating between academia and various other roles, including serving as an officer during World War I and a hospital porter during World War II. When in academia Wittgenstein was taught by Bertrand Russell, and he himself taught at Cambridge.
He began laying the groundwork for Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus while in the trenches, and published it after the end of the war. It has since come to be considered one of the most important works of 20th century philosophy. After publishing it, Wittgenstein concluded that it had solved all philosophical problemsβso he never published another book-length work in his lifetime.
The book itself is divided into a series of short, self-evident statements, followed by sub-statements elucidating on their parent statement, sub-sub-statements, and so on. These statements explore the nature of philosophy, our understanding of the world around us, and how language fits in to it all. These views later came to be known as βLogical Atomism.β
This translation, while credited to C. K. Ogden, is actually mostly the work of F. P. Ramsey, one of Ogdenβs students. Ramsey completed the translation when he was just 19 years of age. The translation was personally revised and approved by Wittgenstein himself, who, though he was Austrian, had spent much of his life in England.
Much of the Tractatusβ meaning is complex and difficult to unpack. It is still being interpreted and explored to this day.
Read free book Β«Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein (i want to read a book .txt) πΒ» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Ludwig Wittgenstein
Read book online Β«Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein (i want to read a book .txt) πΒ». Author - Ludwig Wittgenstein
And this is the case, for the symbols βpβ and βqβ presuppose ββ¨β, β~β, etc. If the sign βpβ in βpβ¨qβ does not stand for a complex sign, then by itself it cannot have sense; but then also the signs βpβ¨pβ, βp.pβ, etc. which have the same sense as βpβ have no sense. If, however, βpβ¨pβ has no sense, then also βpβ¨qβ can have no sense.
5.5151Must the sign of the negative proposition be constructed by means of the sign of the positive? Why should one not be able to express the negative proposition by means of a negative fact? (Like: if βaβ does not stand in a certain relation to βbβ, it could express that aRb is not the case.)
But here also the negative proposition is indirectly constructed with the positive.
The positive proposition must presuppose the existence of the negative proposition and conversely.
5.52If the values of ΞΎ are the total values of a function fβ‘x for all values of x, then Nβ‘(ΞΎβΎ)=~(βx).fβ‘x.
5.521I separate the concept all from the truth-function.
Frege and Russell have introduced generality in connection with the logical product or the logical sum. Then it would be difficult to understand the propositions β(βx).fβ‘xβ and β(x).fβ‘xβ in which both ideas lie concealed.
5.522That which is peculiar to the βsymbolism of generalityβ is firstly, that it refers to a logical prototype, and secondly, that it makes constants prominent.
5.523The generality symbol occurs as an argument.
5.524If the objects are given, therewith are all objects also given.
If the elementary propositions are given, then therewith all elementary propositions are also given.
5.525It is not correct to render the proposition β(βx).fβ‘xββ βas Russell doesβ βin the words βfβ‘x is possible.β
Certainty, possibility or impossibility of a state of affairs are not expressed by a proposition but by the fact that an expression is a tautology, a significant proposition or a contradiction.
That precedent to which one would always appeal, must be present in the symbol itself.
5.526One can describe the world completely by completely generalized propositions, i.e. without from the outset coordinating any name with a definite object.
In order then to arrive at the customary way of expression we need simply say after an expression βthere is one and only one x, whichβ ββ β¦β: and this x is a.
5.5261A completely generalized proposition is like every other proposition composite. (This is shown by the fact that in β(βx,Ο).Οxβ we must mention βΟβ and βxβ separately. Both stand independently in signifying relations to the world as in the ungeneralized proposition.)
A characteristic of a composite symbol: it has something in common with other symbols.
5.5262The truth or falsehood of every proposition alters something in the general structure of the world. And the range which is allowed to its structure by the totality of elementary propositions is exactly that which the completely general propositions delimit.
(If an elementary proposition is true, then, at any rate, there is one more elementary proposition true.)
5.53Identity of the object I express by identity of the sign and not by means of a sign of identity. Difference of the objects by difference of the signs.
5.5301That identity is not a relation between objects is obvious. This becomes very clear if, for example, one considers the proposition β(x):fβ‘x.β.x=aβ. What this proposition says is simply that only a satisfies the function f, and not that only such things satisfy the function f which have a certain relation to a.
One could of course say that in fact only a has this relation to a, but in order to express this we should need the sign of identity itself.
5.5302Russellβs definition of β=β wonβt do; because according to it one cannot say that two objects have all their properties in common. (Even if this proposition is never true, it is nevertheless significant.)
5.5303Roughly speaking: to say of two things that they are identical is nonsense, and to say of one thing that it is identical with itself is to say nothing.
5.531I write therefore not βfβ‘(a,b).a=bβ but βfβ‘(aa)β (or βfβ‘(bb)β). And not βfβ‘(a,b).~a=bβ, but βfβ‘(a,b)β.
5.532And analogously: not β(βx,y).fβ‘(x,y).x=yβ, but β(βx).fβ‘(x,x)β; and not β(βx,y).fβ‘(x,y).~x=yβ, but β(βx,y).fβ‘(x,y)β.
(Therefore instead of Russellβs β(βx,y).fβ‘(x,y)β: β(βx,y).fβ‘(x,y).β¨.(βx).fβ‘(x,x)β.)
5.5321Instead of β(x):fβ‘xβx=aβ we therefore write e.g. β(βx).fβ‘x.β.fβ‘a:~(βx,y).fβ‘x.fβ‘yβ.
And if the proposition βonly one x satisfies fβ‘()β reads: β(βx).fβ‘x:~(βx,y).fβ‘x.fβ‘yβ.
5.533The identity sign is therefore not an essential constituent of logical notation.
5.534And we see that the apparent propositions like: βa=aβ, βa=b.b=c.βa=cβ, β(x).x=xβ. β
Comments (0)