Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein (i want to read a book .txt) ๐
Description
Ludwig Wittgenstein is considered by many to be one of the most important philosophers of the 20th century. He was born in Vienna to an incredibly rich family, but he gave away his inheritance and spent his life alternating between academia and various other roles, including serving as an officer during World War I and a hospital porter during World War II. When in academia Wittgenstein was taught by Bertrand Russell, and he himself taught at Cambridge.
He began laying the groundwork for Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus while in the trenches, and published it after the end of the war. It has since come to be considered one of the most important works of 20th century philosophy. After publishing it, Wittgenstein concluded that it had solved all philosophical problemsโso he never published another book-length work in his lifetime.
The book itself is divided into a series of short, self-evident statements, followed by sub-statements elucidating on their parent statement, sub-sub-statements, and so on. These statements explore the nature of philosophy, our understanding of the world around us, and how language fits in to it all. These views later came to be known as โLogical Atomism.โ
This translation, while credited to C. K. Ogden, is actually mostly the work of F. P. Ramsey, one of Ogdenโs students. Ramsey completed the translation when he was just 19 years of age. The translation was personally revised and approved by Wittgenstein himself, who, though he was Austrian, had spent much of his life in England.
Much of the Tractatusโ meaning is complex and difficult to unpack. It is still being interpreted and explored to this day.
Read free book ยซTractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein (i want to read a book .txt) ๐ยป - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Ludwig Wittgenstein
Read book online ยซTractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein (i want to read a book .txt) ๐ยป. Author - Ludwig Wittgenstein
The theory of classes is altogether superfluous in mathematics.
This is connected with the fact that the generality which we need in mathematics is not the accidental one.
6.1The propositions of logic are tautologies.
6.11The propositions of logic therefore say nothing. (They are the analytical propositions.)
6.111Theories which make a proposition of logic appear substantial are always false. One could e.g. believe that the words โtrueโ and โfalseโ signify two properties among other properties, and then it would appear as a remarkable fact that every proposition possesses one of these properties. This now by no means appears self-evident, no more so than the proposition โAll roses are either yellow or redโ would seem even if it were true. Indeed our proposition now gets quite the character of a proposition of natural science and this is a certain symptom of its being falsely understood.
6.112The correct explanation of logical propositions must give them a peculiar position among all propositions.
6.113It is the characteristic mark of logical propositions that one can perceive in the symbol alone that they are true; and this fact contains in itself the whole philosophy of logic. And so also it is one of the most important facts that the truth or falsehood of non-logical propositions can not be recognized from the propositions alone.
6.12The fact that the propositions of logic are tautologies shows the formalโ โlogicalโ โproperties of language, of the world.
That its constituent parts connected together in this way give a tautology characterizes the logic of its constituent parts.
In order that propositions connected together in a definite way may give a tautology they must have definite properties of structure. That they give a tautology when so connected shows therefore that they possess these properties of structure.
6.1201That e.g. the propositions โpโ and โ~pโ in the connection โ~(p.~p)โ give a tautology shows that they contradict one another. That the propositions โpโqโ, โpโ and โqโ connected together in the form โ(pโq).(p):โ:(q)โ give a tautology shows that q follows from p and pโq. That โ(x).fโกx:โ:fโกaโ is a tautology shows that fโกa follows from (x).fโกx, etc. etc.
6.1202It is clear that we could have used for this purpose contradictions instead of tautologies.
6.1203In order to recognize a tautology as such, we can, in cases in which no sign of generality occurs in the tautology, make use of the following intuitive method: I write instead of โpโ, โqโ, โrโ, etc., โTpFโ, โTqFโ, โTrFโ, etc. The truth-combinations I express by brackets, e.g.:
and the coordination of the truth or falsity of the whole proposition with the truth-combinations of the truth-arguments by lines in the following way:
This sign, for example, would therefore present the proposition pโq. Now I will proceed to inquire whether such a proposition as ~(p.~p) (The Law of Contradiction) is a tautology. The form โ~ฮพโ is written in our notation
the form โฮพ.ฮทโ thus:โ โ
Hence the proposition ~(p.~q) runs thus:โ โ
If here we put โpโ instead of โqโ and examine the combination of the outermost T and F with the innermost, it is seen that the truth of the whole proposition is coordinated with all the truth-combinations of its argument, its falsity with none of the truth-combinations.
6.121The propositions of logic demonstrate the logical properties of propositions, by combining them into propositions which say nothing.
This method could be called a zero-method. In a logical proposition propositions are brought into equilibrium with one another, and the state of equilibrium then shows how these propositions must be logically constructed.
6.122Whence it follows that we can get on without logical propositions, for we can recognize in an adequate notation the formal properties of the propositions by mere inspection.
6.1221If for example two propositions โpโ and โqโ give a tautology in the connection โpโqโ, then it is clear that q follows from p.
E.g. that โqโ follows from โpโq.pโ we see from these two propositions themselves, but we can also show it by combining them to โqโ follows from โpโq.p:โ:qโ and then showing that this is a tautology.
6.1222This throws light on the question why logical propositions can no more be empirically confirmed than they can be empirically refuted. Not only must a proposition of logic be incapable of being contradicted by any possible experience, but it must also be incapable of being confirmed by any such.
6.1223It now becomes clear why we often feel as though โlogical truthsโ must be โpostulatedโ by us. We can in fact postulate them in so far as we can postulate an adequate notation.
6.1224It also becomes clear why logic has been called the theory of forms and of inference.
6.123It is clear that the laws of logic cannot themselves obey further logical laws.
(There is not, as Russell supposed, for every โtypeโ a special law of contradiction; but one is sufficient, since it is not applied to itself.)
6.1231The mark of logical propositions is not their general
Comments (0)