American library books ยป Other ยป The Problems of Philosophy by Bertrand Russell (best novels of all time txt) ๐Ÿ“•

Read book online ยซThe Problems of Philosophy by Bertrand Russell (best novels of all time txt) ๐Ÿ“•ยป.   Author   -   Bertrand Russell



1 ... 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 ... 44
Go to page:
because, although my premises and my conclusion are true, the conclusion does not follow from the premises.

But are we to say that nothing is knowledge except what is validly deduced from true premises? Obviously we cannot say this. Such a definition is at once too wide and too narrow. In the first place, it is too wide, because it is not enough that our premises should be โ€œtrue,โ€ they must also be โ€œknown.โ€ The man who believes that Mr. Balfour was the late Prime Minister may proceed to draw valid deductions from the true premise that the late Prime Ministerโ€™s name began with a B, but he cannot be said to โ€œknowโ€ the conclusions reached by these deductions. Thus we shall have to amend our definition by saying that knowledge is what is validly deduced from โ€œknownโ€ premises. This, however, is a circular definition: it assumes that we already know what is meant by โ€œknown premises.โ€ It can, therefore, at best define one sort of knowledge, the sort we call derivative, as opposed to intuitive knowledge. We may say: โ€œDerivative knowledge is what is validly deduced from premises known intuitively.โ€ In this statement there is no formal defect, but it leaves the definition of โ€œintuitiveโ€ knowledge still to seek.

Leaving on one side, for the moment, the question of intuitive knowledge, let us consider the above suggested definition of derivative knowledge. The chief objection to it is that it unduly limits knowledge. It constantly happens that people entertain a true belief, which has grown up in them because of some piece of intuitive knowledge from which it is capable of being validly inferred, but from which it has not, as a matter of fact, been inferred by any logical process.

Take, for example, the beliefs produced by reading. If the newspapers announce the death of the King, we are fairly well justified in believing that the King is dead, since this is the sort of announcement which would not be made if it were false. And we are quite amply justified in believing that the newspaper asserts that the King is dead. But here the intuitive knowledge upon which our belief is based is knowledge of the existence of sense-data derived from looking at the print which gives the news. This knowledge scarcely rises into consciousness, except in a person who cannot read easily. A child may be aware of the shapes of the letters, and pass gradually and painfully to a realization of their meaning. But anybody accustomed to reading passes at once to what the letters mean, and is not aware, except on reflection, that he has derived this knowledge from the sense-data called seeing the printed letters. Thus although a valid inference from the-letters to their meaning is possible, and could be performed by the reader, it is not in fact performed, since he does not in fact perform any operation which can be called logical inference. Yet it would be absurd to say that the reader does not โ€œknowโ€ that the newspaper announces the Kingโ€™s death.

We must, therefore, admit as derivative knowledge whatever is the result of intuitive knowledge even if by mere association, provided there is a valid logical connection, and the person in question could become aware of this connection by reflection. There are in fact many ways, besides logical inference, by which we pass from one belief to another: the passage from the print to its meaning illustrates these ways. These ways may be called โ€œpsychological inference.โ€ We shall, then, admit such psychological inference as a means of obtaining derivative knowledge, provided there is a discoverable logical inference which runs parallel to the psychological inference. This renders our definition of derivative knowledge less precise than we could wish, since the word โ€œdiscoverableโ€ is vague: it does not tell us how much reflection may be needed in order to make the discovery. But in fact โ€œknowledgeโ€ is not a precise conception: it merges into โ€œprobable opinion,โ€ as we shall see more fully in the course of the present chapter. A very precise definition, therefore, should not be sought, since any such definition must be more or less misleading.

The chief difficulty in regard to knowledge, however, does not arise over derivative knowledge, but over intuitive knowledge. So long as we are dealing with derivative knowledge, we have the test of intuitive knowledge to fall back upon. But in regard to intuitive beliefs, it is by no means easy to discover any criterion by which to distinguish some as true and others as erroneous. In this question it is scarcely possible to reach any very precise result: all our knowledge of truths is infected with some degree of doubt, and a theory which ignored this fact would be plainly wrong. Something may be done, however, to mitigate the difficulties of the question.

Our theory of truth, to begin with, supplies the possibility of distinguishing certain truths as โ€œself-evidentโ€ in a sense which ensures infallibility. When a belief is true, we said, there is a corresponding fact, in which the several objects of the belief form a single complex. The belief is said to constitute โ€œknowledgeโ€ of this fact, provided it fulfils those further somewhat vague conditions which we have been considering in the present chapter. But in regard to any fact, besides the knowledge constituted by belief, we may also have the kind of knowledge constituted by โ€œperceptionโ€ (taking this word in its widest possible sense). For example, if you know the hour of the sunset, you can at that hour know the fact that the sun is setting: this is knowledge of the fact by way of knowledge of โ€œtruthsโ€; but you can also, if the weather is fine, look to the west and actually see the setting sun: you then know the same fact by the way of knowledge of โ€œthings.โ€

Thus in regard to any complex fact, there are, theoretically, two ways in which it may be known: (1) by means of a judgement, in which its several

1 ... 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 ... 44
Go to page:

Free e-book: ยซThe Problems of Philosophy by Bertrand Russell (best novels of all time txt) ๐Ÿ“•ยป   -   read online now on website american library books (americanlibrarybooks.com)

Comments (0)

There are no comments yet. You can be the first!
Add a comment