The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) π
Those not self-conscious and self-willed are constantly acting from self-interested motives, but clothing these in various garbs. Watch those people closely in the light of Stirner's teaching, and they seem to be hypocrites, they have so many good moral and religious plans of which self-interest is at the end and bottom; but they, we may believe, do not know that this is more than a coincidence.
In Stirner we have the philosophical foundation for political liberty. His interest in the practical development of egoism to the dissolution of the State and the union of free men is clear and pronounced, and harmonizes perfectly with the economic philosophy of Josiah Warren. Allowing for difference of temperament and language, there is a substantial agreement between Stirner and Proudhon. Each would be free, and sees in every increase of the number of free people and their intelligence an a
Read free book Β«The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) πΒ» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Max Stirner
- Performer: -
Read book online Β«The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner (most read books txt) πΒ». Author - Max Stirner
this way they would finally learn to play the flute. Luther, with whom the
so-called Middle Ages end, was the first who understood that the man himself
must become other than he was if he wanted to comprehend truth -- must become
as true as truth itself. Only he who already has truth in his belief, only he
who believes in it, can become a partaker of it; i.e. only the believer
finds it accessible and sounds its depths. Only that organ of man which is
able to blow can attain the further capacity of flute-playing, and only that
man can become a partaker of truth who has the right organ for it. He who is
capable of thinking only what is sensuous, objective, pertaining to things,
figures to himself in truth only what pertains to things. But truth is spirit,
stuff altogether inappreciable by the senses, and therefore only for the
"higher consciousness," not for that which is "earthly-minded."
With Luther, accordingly, dawns the perception that truth, because it is a
thought, is only for the thinking man. And this is to say that man must
henceforth take an utterly different standpoint, to wit, the heavenly,
believing, scientific standpoint, or that of thought in relation to its
object, the -- thought -- that of mind in relation to mind. Consequently:
only the like apprehend the like. "You are like the spirit that you
understand."(47)
Because Protestantism broke the medieval hierarchy, the opinion could take
root that hierarchy in general had been shattered by it, and it could be
wholly overlooked that it was precisely a "reformation," and so a
reinvigoration of the antiquated hierarchy. That medieval hierarchy had been
only a weakly one, as it had to let all possible barbarism of unsanctified
things run on uncoerced beside it, and it was the Reformation that first
steeled the power of hierarchy. If Bruno Bauer thinks:(48) "As the Reformation
was mainly the abstract rending of the religious principle from art, State,
and science, and so its liberation from those powers with which it had joined
itself in the antiquity of the church and in the hierarchy of the Middle Ages,
so too the theological and ecclesiastical movements which proceeded from the
Reformation are only the consistent carrying out of this abstraction of the
religious principle from the other powers of humanity," I regard precisely the
opposite as correct, and think that the dominion of spirits, or freedom of
mind (which comes to the same thing), was never before so all-embracing and
all-powerful, because the present one, instead of rending the religious
principle from art, State, and science, lifted the latter altogether out of
secularity into the "realm of spirit" and made them religious.
Luther and Descartes have been appropriately put side by side in their "He who
believes in God" and "I think, therefore I am" (cogito, ergo sum). Man's
heaven is thought -- mind. Everything can be wrested from him, except thought,
except faith. Particular faith, like faith of Zeus, Astarte, Jehovah, Allah,
may be destroyed, but faith itself is indestructible. In thought is freedom.
What I need and what I hunger for is no longer granted to me by any grace,
by the Virgin Mary. by intercession of the saints, or by the binding and
loosing church, but I procure it for myself. In short, my being (the sum) is
a living in the heaven of thought, of mind, a cogitare. But I myself am
nothing else than mind, thinking mind (according to Descartes), believing mind
(according to Luther). My body I am not; my flesh may suffer from appetites
or pains. I am not my flesh, but I am mind, only mind.
This thought runs through the history of the Reformation till today.
Only by the more modern philosophy since Descartes has a serious effort been
made to bring Christianity to complete efficacy, by exalting the "scientific
consciousness." to be the only true and valid one. Hence it begins with
absolute doubt, dubitare, with grinding common consciousness to atoms, with
turning away from everything that "mind," "thought," does not legitimate. To
it Nature counts for nothing; the opinion of men, their "human precepts,"
for nothing: and it does not rest till it has brought reason into everything,
and can say "The real is the rational, and only the rational is the real."
Thus it has at last brought mind, reason, to victory; and everything is mind,
because everything is rational, because all nature, as well as even the most
perverse opinions of men, contains reason; for "all must serve for the best,"
i. e., lead to the victory of reason.
Descartes's dubitare contains the decided statement that only cogitare,
thought, mind -- is. A complete break with "common" consciousness, which
ascribes reality to irrational things! Only the rational is, only mind is!
This is the principle of modern philosophy, the genuine Christian principle.
Descartes in his own time discriminated the body sharply from the mind, and
"the spirit 'tis that builds itself the body," says Goethe.
But this philosophy itself, Christian philosophy, still does not get rid of
the rational, and therefore inveighs against the "merely subjective," against
"fancies, fortuities, arbitrariness," etc. What it wants is that the divine
should become visible in everything, and all consciousness become a knowing of
the divine, and man behold God everywhere; but God never is, without the
devil. For this very reason the name of philosopher is not to be given to
him who has indeed open eyes for the things of the world, a clear and
undazzled gaze, a correct judgment about the world, but who sees in the world
just the world, in objects only objects, and, in short, everything prosaically
as it is; but he alone is a philosopher who sees, and points out or
demonstrates, heaven in the world, the supernal in the earthly, the --
divine in the mundane. The former may be ever so wise, there is no getting
away from this:
What wise men see not by their wisdom's art Is practiced simply by a childlike heart.(49)It takes this childlike heart, this eye for the divine, to make a philosopher.
The first-named man has only a "common" consciousness, but he who knows the
divine, and knows how to tell it, has a "scientific" one. On this ground Bacon
was turned out of the realm of philosophers. And certainly what is called
English philosophy seems to have got no further than to the discoveries of
so-called "clear heads," e. g. Bacon and Hume. The English did not know how
to exalt the simplicity of the childlike heart to philosophic significance,
did not know how to make -- philosophers out of childlike hearts. This is as
much as to say, their philosophy was not able to become theological or
theology, and yet it is only as theology that it can really live itself
out, complete itself. The field of its battle to the death is in theology.
Bacon did not trouble himself about theological questions and cardinal points.
Cognition has its object in life. German thought seeks, more than that of
others, to reach the beginnings and fountain-heads of life, and sees no life
till it sees it in cognition itself. Descartes's cogito, ergo sum has the
meaning "One lives only when one thinks." Thinking life is called
"intellectual life"! Only mind lives, its life is the true life. Then, just so
in nature only the "eternal laws," the mind or the reason of nature, are its
true life. In man, as in nature, only the thought lives; everything else is
dead! To this abstraction, to the life of generalities or of that which is
lifeless, the history of mind had to come. God, who is spirit, alone lives.
Nothing lives but the ghost.
How can one try to assert of modern philosophy or modern times that they have
reached freedom, since they have not freed us from the power of objectivity?
Or am I perhaps free from a despot when I am not afraid of the personal
potentate, to be sure, but of every infraction of the loving reverence which I
fancy I owe him? The case is the same with modern times. They only changed the
existing objects, the real ruler, into conceived objects, i.e. into
ideas, before which the old respect not only was not lost, but increased in
intensity. Even if people snapped their fingers at God and the devil in their
former crass reality, people devoted only the greater attention to their
ideas. "They are rid of the Evil One; evil is left."(50) The decision having
once been made not to let oneself be imposed on any longer by the extant and
palpable, little scruple was felt about revolting against the existing State
or overturning the existing laws; but to sin against the idea of the State,
not to submit to the idea of law, who would have dared that? So one remained
a "citizen" and a "law-respecting," loyal man; yes, one seemed to himself to
be only so much more law-respecting, the more rationalistically one abrogated
the former defective law in order to do homage to the "spirit of the law." In
all this the objects had only suffered a change of form; they had remained in
their preponderance and pre-eminence; in short, one was still involved in
obedience and possessedness, lived in reflection, and had an object on which
one reflected, which one respected, and before which one felt reverence and
fear. One had done nothing but transform the things into conceptions of
the things, into thoughts and ideas, whereby one's dependence became all the
more intimate and indissoluble. So, e. g., it is not hard to emancipate
oneself from the commands of parents, or to set aside the admonitions of uncle
and aunt, the entreaties of brother and sister; but the renounced obedience
easily gets into one's conscience, and the less one does give way to the
individual demands, because he rationalistically, by his own reason,
recognizes them to be unreasonable, so much the more conscientiously does he
hold fast to filial piety and family love, and so much the harder is it for
him to forgive himself a trespass against the conception which he has formed
of family love and of filial duty. Released from dependence as regards the
existing family, one falls into the more binding dependence on the idea of the
family; one is ruled by the spirit of the family. The family consisting of
John, Maggie, etc., whose dominion has become powerless, is only internalized,
being left as "family" in general, to which one just applies the old saying,
"We must obey God rather than man," whose significance here is this: "I
cannot, to be sure, accommodate myself to your senseless requirements, but, as
my 'family,' you still remain the object of my love and care"; for "the
Comments (0)