Sixteen Experimental Investigations from the Harvard Psychological Laboratory by Hugo Münsterberg (100 books to read .txt) 📕
[5] Dodge, Raymond, PSYCHOLOGICAL REVIEW, 1900, VII., p. 456.
[6] Graefe, A., Archiv f. Ophthalmologie, 1895, XLI., 3, S. 136.
This explanation of Graefe is not to be admitted, however, since in the case of eye-movement there are muscular sensations of one's own activity, which are not present when one merely sits in a coach. These sensations of eye-movement are in all cases so intimately connected with our perception of the movement of objects, that they may not be in this case simpl
Read free book «Sixteen Experimental Investigations from the Harvard Psychological Laboratory by Hugo Münsterberg (100 books to read .txt) 📕» - read online or download for free at americanlibrarybooks.com
- Author: Hugo Münsterberg
- Performer: -
Read book online «Sixteen Experimental Investigations from the Harvard Psychological Laboratory by Hugo Münsterberg (100 books to read .txt) 📕». Author - Hugo Münsterberg
nothing to do with the golden section.
Since Fechner, the chief investigation in the æsthetics of simple
forms is that of Witmer, in 1893.[1] Only a small part of his work
relates to horizontal division, but enough to show what seems to me a
radical defect in statistical method, namely, that of accepting a
general average of the average judgments of the several subjects, as
‘the most pleasing relation’ or ‘the most pleasing proportion.’[2]
Such a total average may fall wholly without the range of judgments of
every subject concerned, and tells us nothing certain about the
specific judgments of any one. Even in the case of the individual
subject, if he shows in the course of long experimentation that he has
two distinct sets of judgments, it is not valid to say that his real
norm lies between the two; much less when several subjects are
concerned. If averages are data to be psychophysically explained, they
must fall well within actual individual ranges of judgment, else they
correspond to no empirically determinable psychophysical processes.
Each individual is a locus of possible æsthetic satisfactions. Since
such a locus is our ultimate basis for interpretation, it is inept to
choose, as ‘the most pleasing proportion,’ one that may have no
correspondent empirical reference. The normal or ideal individual,
which such a norm implies, is not a psychophysical entity which may
serve as a basis of explanation, but a mathematical construction.
[1] Witmer, Lightner: ‘Zur experimentellen Aesthetik einfacher
räumlicher Formverhältnisse,’ Phil. Studien, 1893, IX., S.
96-144, 209-263.
This criticism would apply to judgments of unequal division on either
side the center of a horizontal line. It would apply all the more to
any general average of judgments including both sides, for, as we
shall soon see, the judgments of individuals differ materially on the
two sides, and this difference itself may demand its explanation. And
if we should include within this average, judgments above and below
the center of a vertical line, we should have under one heading four
distinct sets of averages, each of which, in the individual cases,
might show important variations from the others, and therefore require
some variation of explanation. And yet that great leveller, the
general average, has obliterated these vital differences, and is
recorded as indicating the ‘most pleasing proportion.’[3] That such an
average falls near the golden section is immaterial. Witmer himself,
as we shall see,[4] does not set much store by this coincidence as a
starting point for explanation, since he is averse to any mathematical
interpretation, but he does consider the average in question
representative of the most pleasing division.
[2] op. cit., 212-215.
[3] Witmer: op. cit., S. 212-215.
[4] op. cit., S. 262.
I shall now, before proceeding to the details of the experiment to be
recorded, review, very briefly, former interpretative tendencies.
Zeising found that the golden section satisfied his demand for unity
and infinity in the same beautiful object.[5] In the golden section,
says Wundt,[6] there is a unity involving the whole; it is therefore
more beautiful than symmetry, according to the æsthetic principle that
that unification of spatial forms which occurs without marked effort,
which, however, embraces the greater manifold, is the more pleasing.
But to me this manifold, to be æsthetic, must be a sensible manifold,
and it is still a question whether the golden section set of relations
has an actual correlate in sensations. Witmer,[7] however, wrote, at
the conclusion of his careful researches, that scientific æsthetics
allows no more exact statement, in interpretation of the golden
section, than that it forms ‘die rechte Mitte’ between a too great and
a too small variety. Nine years later, in 1902, he says[8] that the
preference for proportion over symmetry is not a demand for an
equality of ratios, but merely for greater variety, and that ‘the
amount of unlikeness or variety that is pleasing will depend upon the
general character of the object, and upon the individual’s grade of
intelligence and æsthetic taste.’ Külpe[9] sees in the golden section
‘a special case of the constancy of the relative sensible
discrimination, or of Weber’s law.’ The division of a line at the
golden section produces ‘apparently equal differences’ between minor
and major, and major and whole. It is ‘the pleasingness of apparently
equal differences.’
[5] Zelsing, A.: ‘Aesthetische Forschungen,’ 1855, S. 172;
‘Neue Lehre von den Proportionen des menschlichen Körpera,’
1854, S. 133-174.
[6] Wundt, W.: ‘Physiologische Psychologie,’ 4te Aufl.,
Leipzig, 1893, Bd. II., S. 240 ff.
[7] op. cit., S. 262.
[8] Witmer, L.: ‘Analytical Psychology,’ Boston, 1902, p. 74.
[9] Külpe, O.: ‘Outlines of Psychology,’ Eng. Trans., London,
1895, pp. 253-255.
These citations show, in brief form, the history of the interpretation
of our pleasure in unequal division. Zeising and Wundt were alike in
error in taking the golden section as the norm. Zeising used it to
support a philosophical theory of the beautiful. Wundt and others too
hastily conclude that the mathematical ratios, intellectually
discriminated, are also sensibly discriminated, and form thus the
basis of our æsthetic pleasure. An extension of this principle would
make our pleasure in any arrangement of forms depend on the
mathematical relations of their parts. We should, of course, have no
special reason for choosing one set of relationships rather than
another, nor for halting at any intricacy of formulæ. But we cannot
make experimental æsthetics a branch of applied mathematics. A theory,
if we are to have psychological explanation at all, must be pertinent
to actual psychic experience. Witmer, while avoiding and condemning
mathematical explanation, does not attempt to push interpretation
beyond the honored category of unity in variety, which is applicable
to anything, and, in principle, is akin to Zeising’s unity and
infinity. We wish to know what actual psychophysical functionings
correspond to this unity in variety. Külpe’s interpretation is such an
attempt, but it seems clear that Weber’s law cannot be applied to the
division at the golden section. It would require of us to estimate the
difference between the long side and the short side to be equal to
that of the long side and the whole. A glance at the division shows
that such complex estimation would compare incomparable facts, since
the short and the long parts are separated, while the long part is
inclosed in the whole. Besides, such an interpretation could not apply
to divisions widely variant from the golden section.
This paper, as I said, reports but the beginnings of an investigation
into unequal division, confined as it is to results obtained from the
division of a simple horizontal line, and to variations introduced as
hints towards interpretation. The tests were made in a partially
darkened room. The apparatus rested on a table of ordinary height, the
part exposed to the subject consisting of an upright screen, 45 cm.
high by 61 cm. broad, covered with black cardboard, approximately in
the center of which was a horizontal opening of considerable size,
backed by opal glass. Between the glass and the cardboard, flush with
the edges of the opening so that no stray light could get through, a
cardboard slide was inserted from behind, into which was cut the
exposed figure. A covered electric light illuminated the figure with a
yellowish-white light, so that all the subject saw, besides a dim
outline of the apparatus and the walls of the room, was the
illuminated figure. An upright strip of steel, 1½ mm. wide, movable in
either direction horizontally by means of strings, and controlled by
the subject, who sat about four feet in front of the table, divided
the horizontal line at any point. On the line, of course, this
appeared as a movable dot. The line itself was arbitrarily made 160
mm. long, and 1½ mm. wide. The subject was asked to divide the line
unequally at the most pleasing place, moving the divider from one end
slowly to the other, far enough to pass outside any pleasing range,
or, perhaps, quite off the line; then, having seen the divider at all
points of the line, he moved it back to that position which appealed
to him as most pleasing. Record having been made of this, by means of
a millimeter scale, the subject, without again going off the line,
moved to the pleasing position on the other side of the center. He
then moved the divider wholly off the line, and made two more
judgments, beginning his movement from the other end of the line.
These four judgments usually sufficed for the simple line for one
experiment. In the course of the experimentation each of nine subjects
gave thirty-six such judgments on either side the center, or
seventy-two in all.
In Fig. 1, I have represented graphically the results of these
judgments. The letters at the left, with the exception of X, mark
the subjects. Beginning with the most extreme judgments on either side
the center, I have erected modes to represent the number of judgments
made within each ensuing five millimeters, the number in each case
being denoted by the figure at the top of the mode. The two vertical
dot-and-dash lines represent the means of the several averages of all
the subjects, or the total averages. The short lines, dropped from
each of the horizontals, mark the individual averages of the divisions
either side the center, and at X these have been concentrated into
one line. Subject E obviously shows two pretty distinct fields of
choice, so that it would have been inaccurate to condense them all
into one average. I have therefore given two on each side the center,
in each case subsuming the judgments represented by the four end modes
under one average. In all, sixty judgments were made by E on each
half the line. Letter E¹ represents the first thirty-six; E² the
full number. A comparison of the two shows how easily averages shift;
how suddenly judgments may concentrate in one region after having been
for months fairly uniformly distributed. The introduction of one more
subject might have varied the total averages by several points. Table
I. shows the various averages and mean variations in tabular form.
TABLE I.
Left. Right.
Div. M.V. Div. M.V.
A 54 2.6 50 3.4
B 46 4.5 49 5.7
C 75 1.8 71 1.6
D 62 4.4 56 4.1
E¹ 57 10.7 60 8.7
F 69 2.6 69 1.6
G 65 3.7 64 2.7
H 72 3.8 67 2.1
J 46 1.9 48 1.3
— – — –
Total 60 3.9 59 3.5
Golden Section = 61.1.
¹These are E‘s general averages on 36 judgments. Fig. 1,
however, represents two averages on each side the center, for
which the figures are, on the left, 43 with M.V. 3.6; and 66
with M.V. 5.3. On the right, 49, M.V. 3.1; and 67, M.V. 2.7.
For the full sixty judgments, his total average was 63 on the
left, and 65 on the right, with mean variations of 9.8 and 7.1
respectively. The four that E² in Fig. 1 shows graphically
were, for the left, 43 with M.V. 3.6; and 68, M.V. 5.1. On the
right, 49, M.V. 3.1; and 69, M.V. 3.4.
[Illustration: FIG. 1.]
Results such as are given in Fig. 1, appear to warrant the criticism
of former experimentation. Starting with the golden section, we find
the two lines representing the total averages running surprisingly
close to it. This line, however, out of a possible eighteen chances,
only twice (subjects D and G) falls wholly within the mode
representing the maximum number of judgments of any single subject. In
six cases (C twice, F, H, J twice) it falls wholly without any
mode whatever; and in seven (A,
Comments (0)